Democracy and the Politics of Inclusion
Held argues that a ‘‘fair framework’ for the regulation of a community is one that is freely chosen’ and that
members of a political community – citizens – should be able to choose freely the conditions of their own association, and that their choices should constitute the ultimate legitimation of the form and direction of their polity.

So there is a democratic parallel with indigeneity’s concern for personal and collective freedom and an obvious theoretical convergence between these two concepts of power and authority. All encompassing democratic practices limit the power of elites to exclude. Exclusion is not the point of democracy. But at the same time the concept can be more narrowly interpreted to restrict the terms of public engagement in decision-making, even to the point that for minority indigenous groups assimilation into a culturally homogenous polity is positioned as an essential and necessary precondition for full democratic participation. The former Australian Prime Minister, John Howard (1996-2007), developed a powerful assimilationist narrative to counter growing demands for indigenous self-determination: ‘Son you’re Australian; that’s enough for anyone to be became a simple theme of his Prime Ministership.  He was untroubled by the intellectual conflict between socially conservative emphases on homogeneity and the liberal emphases on freedom. Reconciliation and assimilation became the opposite sides of a nationally polarizing debate which contrasted limiting with expansive democratic interpretations.
Underlying the assimilationist narrative was a normative racism as ‘cultural artefact’ meaning that it stands to reason that prejudice influences the ends to which democracy is ordered. But even so it is not true that the modern state is necessarily ‘a compulsory association which organises domination. Democracy, in fact, constrains the capacity of post-colonial states to dominate, and while the state does monopolise coercive power coercion is not always and necessarily negative for indigenous peoples. For example, guaranteed Maori representation in the New Zealand Parliament and the enactment of settlements to grievances under the Treaty of Waitangi when simple majority vote is likely to have prevented either in spite of their foundation in justice and contribution to social stability and cohesion. In recent Australian history it has been the coercive power of the judicial system that has imposed incremental developments in indigenous legal rights on unsympathetic governments. In both cases coercion is justified to pursue fundamentally just objectives over simple populism. There is consequently pragmatic truth in the general observation that: ‘While the state is the burden individuals have to bear to secure their own ends, it is also the basis on which it is possible to safeguard their claims to equal rights and liberties The limiting factor is that democracy only safeguards the right to make these claims; it does not guarantee a political order that will ensure indigenous perceptions of equality and liberty, which are themselves contested.
Liberal political theory developed to respond to religious diversity. It follows that it ought to be able to consider the political and constitutional implications of ethnic diversity. Its purpose is to mediate rather than to mask difference and to resolve not dismiss conflicting ideas.
Men have different views on the empirical end of happiness, and what it consists of, so that as far as happiness is concerned, their will cannot be brought under any common principle, nor thus under an external law harmonizing with the freedom of everyone.

Recognising difference does not counter liberalism’s sacrosanct protection of individual rights. Individual identity must come from somewhere. It is heavily shaped by culture and derives meaning from communal relationships. Differences in political identities contribute to the differences in ideas that democracy is intended to mediate. The ideas that compete for popular ascendency are not confined to abstract philosophical positions; they include the simple proposition that indigenous perspectives ought to be seen and heard in the wider body politic.
The unity of society and the allegiance of its citizens to their common institutions rest not on their espousing one rational conception of the good, but on an agreement as to what is just for free and equal moral persons with different and opposing conceptions of the good.

Indigeneity’s concern with collective rights means that it is also inevitably interested in correcting the effects of colonisation as a serious violation of individual liberty. Indigeneity gives theoretical expression to the recognition of differences based on first occupancy. Its interpretation of political rights evolves in response to its theoretical and political interactions with other discourses; its potency is a function of its engagement with liberal democracy as the prevailing internationally accepted framework of state governance. Together they create opportunities for indigenous peoples to articulate their own conceptions of justice, and democracy is crafted towards its inclusive potential. Indigeneity is concerned with differentiation from the wider polity, but this does not inevitably or necessarily require political separation. Instead
one of the interesting consequences of the encounter between liberalism and its colonial past and present might be a more context-sensitive and multilayered approach to questions of justice, identity, democracy and sovereignty. The result would be a political theory open to new modes of cultural and political belonging.

Such a theory can accord with indigenous aspirations because there need not be any inconsistency between collective group rights and the sovereignty of the total polity. Kymlicka’s argument that the paradigm shift from democracy ‘suppressing to accomodating’ minority ethnic groups in the United States of America has ‘actually played a vital role in consolidating and deepening democracy can be translated into indigenous contexts to add to the rationales for guaranteed indigenous parliamentary representation in Australia, New Zealand and Fiji, for example. In these contexts emphasis on individual rights in isolation from the collective offers no real prospect for securing comprehensive individual freedom or the certainty of equal individual influence over the polity. 
Held outlines four democratic criteria which would, if applied consistently and universally, make states more responsive to indigenous aspirations. Democracy should provide for:
Protection from the arbitrary use of political authority and coercive power…

The involvement of citizens in the determination of the conditions of their association through the provision of their consent in the maintenance and legitimation of regulative institutions…

The creation of the best circumstances for citizens to develop their nature and express their diverse qualities…


These criteria arise because ‘the capability of persons to determine and justify their own actions, with their ability to determine among alternative political programmes is the ‘core of the modern liberal democratic projectOr as Benhabib proposes: ‘the institutions and culture of liberal democracies are sufficiently complex, supple, and decentred so as to allow the expression of difference without fracturing the identity of the body politic or subverting existing forms of political sovereignty.

0 Comments:

Powered by Blogger.

Visitors

Print Friendly Version of this pagePrint Get a PDF version of this webpagePDF


 download University Notes apps for android

Popular Posts

Flag Counter